Dualist Afterlives: Avicenna and Mullā Ṣadrā

Publish Year: 1400
نوع سند: مقاله ژورنالی
زبان: English
View: 165

This Paper With 25 Page And PDF Format Ready To Download

  • Certificate
  • من نویسنده این مقاله هستم

استخراج به نرم افزارهای پژوهشی:

لینک ثابت به این Paper:

شناسه ملی سند علمی:

JR_JTIS-1-1_003

تاریخ نمایه سازی: 18 دی 1401

Abstract:

Subscribing to the principles of logically valid reasoning and parsimony of presuppositions in the framework of a religion that hinges on a revealed eschatological message, the medieval Islamic philosophers were bound to interpret the Qurʾānic account of the afterlife in ways that may have compromised at least some of its literal meanings. However, to what extent precisely do these interpretations go against the grain of Revelation has to be determined separately in each particular case. Wholesale statements regarding the alleged coherence or incoherence of general types of philosophical theories with Revelation risk neglecting important variations between theories, and thereby rendering us blind to the scope of possibilities in the concepts involved. From this perspective, I will consider the eschatological implications of the psychological theories of Avicenna and Mullā Ṣadrā, who both subscribe to a dualistic view of human being and consequently claim that the afterlife does not concern one's body. Two questions will then emerge as especially central to dualistic accounts of the afterlife. (۱) How do we make sense of the kind of first-personality that must be an irreducible constituent of existence in the hereafter, provided that the latter fulfills the eschatological promise given in the Revelation? For in order to be a justified reward or punishment for my acts in this life, the afterlife must be in an equally strong sense mine. In the Arabic Peripatetic tradition, many of the central doctrines of which Avicenna and Mullā Ṣadrā subscribe to, individuality entails materiality, which seems to suggest that human being can have a distinctly first-personal existence only when some kind of connection is preserved to the body as the necessary condition of one's individuation. (۲) How do we account for the emphatically sensual descriptions of the hereafter in the Revelation? Again, in the Peripatetic tradition all cognitive acts that involve objects with sensible characteristics require bodily instruments of cognition, in the absence of which the revealed account is in danger of becoming a mere metaphor. In the light of these two questions, I will argue that Avicenna's dualism ends up with a rather narrow conception of the afterlife. He does try to give an account of a genuinely first-personal afterlife, and thereby presents a carefully argued departure from the Peripatetic tradition. But because of the way in which Avicenna separates the soul from the body, Avicennian afterlife is bound to remain exclusively intellectual. Thus, with regard to the second question Avicenna seems forced to interpret the Revelation in almost exclusively metaphorical terms. On the other hand, while following Avicenna in the first question, Mullā Ṣadrā conceives of the separate existence of the human soul in much broader terms than his predecessor. By means of the concepts of mental existence (wujud dhihniyy) and the world of images ('ālam al-mithāl), he ends up with a conception of human afterlife that is rich in terms of experiential content, and thereby potentially more coherent with the revealed account.

Authors

Jari kaukua

Academy of Finland and University of Jyväskylä, Finland

مراجع و منابع این Paper:

لیست زیر مراجع و منابع استفاده شده در این Paper را نمایش می دهد. این مراجع به صورت کاملا ماشینی و بر اساس هوش مصنوعی استخراج شده اند و لذا ممکن است دارای اشکالاتی باشند که به مرور زمان دقت استخراج این محتوا افزایش می یابد. مراجعی که مقالات مربوط به آنها در سیویلیکا نمایه شده و پیدا شده اند، به خود Paper لینک شده اند :
  • Abdel Haleem, M. A. S. (۲۰۱۰). The Qurʾān: English Translation ...
  • Adamson, P., Benevich, F. (۲۰۱۸). The Thought-Experimental Method: Avicenna’s Flying ...
  • Aristotle. (n.d.). De an (III.۵, ۴۳۰a۲۰-۲۵).?Avicenna. (۱۹۵۲). Shifāʾ: Madkhal (I. ...
  • Avicenna. (۲۰۰۵). Shifāʾ: Ilāhiyyāt (M. Marmura, Trans.) Provo: Brigham Young ...
  • Avicenna. (۲۰۱۳). Taʿlīqāt. (S. H. Mousavian, Ed.). Tehran: Iranian Institute ...
  • Avicenna. (۱۸۹۲). al-Ishārāt wa’l-Tanbīhāt (J. Forget,Ed.). Leiden: E. J. Brill ...
  • Avicenna. (۱۹۸۴). al-Mabdaʾ wa’l-Maʿād (A. Nūrānī, Ed.). Tehran: McGill University ...
  • Avicenna. (۱۹۶۹). al-Risāla al-Aḍḥawīya fī al-Maʿād (F. Lucchetta, Ed., VI). ...
  • Avicenna. (n.d.). Mubāḥathāt.??Badawī, A. (۱۹۴۷). Arisṭūʿinda al-ʿArab. Cairo: Maktaba al-Nahḍa ...
  • Benevich. F. (۲۰۱۹). Individuation and Identity in Islamic Philosophy after ...
  • Fārābī, Cf. (۱۹۶۴). al-Siyāsa al-Madanīya al-Mulaqqab bi-Mabādiʾ al-Mawjūdāt (F. Najjār, ...
  • Gutas, D. (۲۰۱۴). Avicenna and the Aristotelian Tradition: Introduction to ...
  • Henrich, D. (۱۹۷۰). Selbstbewußtsein, kritische Einleitung in eine Theorie (R. ...
  • Jambet, C. (۲۰۰۸). Mort et résurrection en islam: Lʼau-delà selon ...
  • Kaukua, J. (۲۰۱۵). Self-Awareness in Islamic Philosophy: Avicenna and Beyond. ...
  • Kalin, I. (۲۰۱۰). Knowledge in Later Islamic Philosophy: Mulla Sadrâ ...
  • Michot, J. R. (۱۹۸۶). La destinée de lʼhomme selon Avicenne: ...
  • Mullā Ṣadrā. (۲۰۰۱). al-Ḥikma al-mutaʿāliya fī al-asfār al-arbaʿa al-ʿaqlīya (S. ...
  • Mullā Ṣadrā. (۱۳۸۴HSh). Mafātīḥ al-ghayb. (N. Habibi, Ed.). Tehran: Sadra ...
  • Reisman, D. C. (۲۰۰۲). The Making of the Avicennan Tradition: ...
  • Suhrawardī. (۱۹۹۹). Ḥikmat al-ishrāq (J. Walbridge and H. Ziai Eds., ...
  • نمایش کامل مراجع